© E.R.Douglas
Temporality, Intentionality, the Hard Problem of Consciousness and the
Causal Mechanisms of Memory in the Brain: Facets of One Ontological Enigma?
E. R. Douglas
1. Introduction
The three greatest
metaphysical questions to confront humanity at the beginning of the
twenty-first century are arguably: What is time? What is mind?
What is the physical origin of the material universe? Each of these perennial issues has generated
a colossal body of philosophical, literary and scientific investigation. However, as is so often the case in our overly
complex epoch, an excessive emphasis on problem analysis, the methodological
hallmark of the previous century, has also led to a paucity in the rigorous
synthesis of such seemingly disparate issues. In this essay, I argue that these three
questions have proven especially difficult to answer on account of a single
underlying enigma, a riddle that turns on the nature of temporal transitivity
and direction.
Investigations of such expansive
questions are traditionally more customary in the humanities than in the
sciences, but it is a central tenet of this essay that both kinds of methodologies
are necessary to their possible resolution(s).
In particular, I adopt the analytically motivated rigor of the sciences,
maximizing the clarity of the disparate issues and concepts at hand, but also motivated
by the humanities’ focus on the function of human agency in the pursuit of
natural truth, I claim rational grounds for drawing a synthesis among the
corresponding problem sets. So on the
one hand, I attempt to explicate such diverse terms as, for example, time, intentionality, causality,
memory and directedness – whose commonly understood definitions leave them too
ambiguous and/or obscure for an analytically empirical methodology. On the other hand, while they prove under
inspection to have a common conceptual thread, its empirical credentials depend
for merit on the acceptance of the phenomenological relationship between the
scientist and nature, or the philosopher and philosopheme, as itself legitimately
evidential. While this step does not
require an endorsement of Protagoras’s relativist claim that man is the measure of all things, we
must nonetheless accept that he remains the measurer
of all that we know.[1]
From the vantage of this
interdisciplinary perspective, it becomes increasingly evident that physics,
and the scientific Weltanschauung
generally, is coming to a crossroads. While there remain many questions without
definitive answers, science as most generally construed now comprises a
patchwork of models and theories that collectively can speak to almost every
conceivable issue in natural philosophy.
Yet, internal inconsistency abounds, and I would further contend that at
least mainstream science has overlooked a very important aspect of nature. Illustrating for the nonce with a metaphor
that may yet prove more than mere metaphor, science has sketched the design of
the cosmos, but the blueprints reproduced remain monochromatic; whereas nature
in all its wonder remains demonstrably colourful.[2] Nonetheless, one can inscribe all the colours
with a single ink – so the metaphor continues – and though it is disputable
whether one can thus entirely characterize their natures, we should at least
attempt such ‘scientific’ descriptions as completely, accurately and truly as
possible.
In particular, I nominate three
classes of ‘empirical’ phenomena that mainstream science has not sufficiently
explored: consciousness, causality and psychological time. With respect to the
first, it has been widely objected that purely physicalist, materialist and
even cognitivist accounts can suffice to explain away (mental) phenomena qua
phenomena (and in particular for our purposes, intentionality, but also notably, qualia or indeed the experience of colour itself). To the second, I ask: does causality as we
perceive it actually equate with a statistical correlation between events as
stipulated in most contemporary analytic accounts and, if so, how did the
universe come to be, and what would that even mean? Finally, the third begs whether ‘time’ really
reduces accurately and completely in all its forms to a static tableau, in
spite of our manifest experience of temporality as profoundly transient and
directed.
Each of these three problem sets is
marked by several possible solutions, theories or philosophical approaches that
one might adopt, some easier, some ‘harder’ or, indeed, some considerably more
‘colourful’ than others. The first and
‘easiest’ solution falls under the name of eliminativism in the philosophy of
mind, but it generalizes to all three of the problem domains we are considering
here. This view relegates all mental
phenomena to instances of mechanistic brain chemistry, but we may regard its
cousin theories equating cause with correlation and time with space
respectively. The more difficult, but
more colourful – ergo, I contend, more ‘empirical’ – approaches involve wrestling
with the underlying hard problems of explicating the emergence and nature of
consciousness and intentionality, temporal transience and direction, as well as
the metaphysics of being, becoming and causality. Although I discuss some of the ‘colourful’
theories available to explain the emphasized phenomena endemic to each domain
of inquiry, my focus throughout this essay remains primarily on distinguishing
eliminativist solutions – which at root simply expurgate their respective
ontologies of the problematic phenomena – from those that do not.
The ultimate thesis of this essay
asserts that the apparent quandaries of these three introduced problem sets are
really each facets of a single, underlying enigma, but I make this case through
several lemmas or staged arguments.
First, I link these disparate concepts (time, mind, cause) by first
explicating their meanings and then identifying how directionality plays a
central role in the interpretation of all three; this comprises the remainder
of section one. Second, I remonstrate
something of a collective bad faith marked by a tendency in the philosophical
and scientific literature to explain the most difficult aspects of each of the
problem sets by smuggling implicit assumptions from the other two respective
problem domains. This discussion
strongly emphasizes the concept of directionality and so also significantly
informs yet a quasi-fourth quandary of import to the natural philosophy of
time: the meaning, origin and nature of the arrow of time. This last matter figures prominently in the
larger problematic, for, in contrast, none of the other ‘empirical’ phenomena I
endorse (consciousness, apparent causality or temporal transience) has
aggravated especially physical scientists so much.
From here, I contend that while there may not
necessarily be clear a priori grounds
to choose one class of explanation over another – i.e., ‘monochromatic’
universe over ‘colourful’ cosmos – to explain the three (or four)
aforementioned quandaries, insofar as metaphysics motivates arguments
introduced in natural philosophy, the principles invoked for one solution should
be employed consistently across the other two problem domains. In this way, I maintain an all or nothing
approach to eliminativism in natural philosophy; the cosmic models we endorse
are either very colourful or very monochromatic, there is little room for
compromise. However, the stage is thus
set to revisit the issue of whether and how science should attempt to explain
the ‘colourfulness’ of the cosmos, and from this more global, human
perspective, I maintain a considerably stronger case presents itself for the
affirmative on the first question through a kind of logical inter-corroboration
of empirical evidence.
As for ‘how’ science should proceed,
both the principle of parsimony and this weave of logical association between
problem domains support theories able to resolve all the aforementioned
difficulties synchronically. Although I
mention a few promising scientific attempts to come to terms with these issues,
a complete review of contemporary research lies beyond this essay’s scope;
notably, I have had to omit due consideration to ideas stemming from Bohm’s
implicate order – I could not do it the justice here it deserves. Finally, I would conclude this introduction
with a small warning: although rigor is desirable, natural philosophy is neither mathematical nor empirical per se, and
the discourse herein is less an analytical proof than a metaphysical sketch
stencilled with plausibility arguments, all hopefully inducing further
dialectical investigation.[3]
1.1 Chronological and Rhealogical Time[4]
It is no great
exaggeration to say ‘time’ has as many meanings as token applications, and yet they
do share a common essence – sufficiently, that most disciplines tacitly assume
that their ‘temporality’ is similar, if not identical, to those of every other field. J. T. Fraser has made great inroads in
explicating this semantic jungle of times,
and his characterization of six sorts of temporality proves an excellent point
of departure. (1975; 1987; 1996; 1998;
1999) Each is distinguished by the
accumulation of novel properties and qualities which emerge in increasingly
complex natural systems to form a nested hierarchy of times. This scheme has proven very useful and
influential, so that one finds its trace etched across the sciences and the
humanities; in particular, the physicist, Rovelli, employs it to argue that a
final theory of cosmology will have ‘no time,’ since the most fundamental
levels of reality lack temporal structure, congruent with Fraser’s atemporality. (Rovelli 1995) In most respects, their schemes agree;
direction corresponds respectively with thermodynamics and life (biotemporality), and both tacitly regard
the present or ‘passing now’ as a
feature properly attributed to the time of (human) intentional agents (nootemporality).
However, I must begin by taking
issue with these two properties, directedness
and transience, as characterized
above. They are in fact both present in Fraser’s
lowest echelon, atemporality, and so by
evolutionary extension pervade all of his levels. In contrast, Rovelli’s scheme highlights the
formulae and physical models of his (meta-) physics, emphasizing the static and
permanent, relegating transience to illusion.
Moreover, direction finds no place in his scheme whatsoever, for the
asymmetry and direction of time are not equivalent, as I show in the next
section. Thus, all other similarities
aside, Rovelli plays Parmenides to Fraser’s Heraclites, and to celebrate this
difference, I introduce a category distinction between species of time to
cleave the distinction sharply: any model or idea of time that invokes transience, even qua illusion, is rhealogical, and those that do not, but are
static, are termed chronological. Moreover – and I argue this further in the
next section – directedness appears to be a feature of all and only rhealogical
models of time, whereas chronological time is devoid of such qualities. Thus, Fraser’s nested times are paradigmatically
rhealogical, whereas all orthodox physical models are chronological.[5]
However, what precisely is this
mysterious transience? This proves to be a surprisingly subtle
question whose answer quickly extends beyond the scope of this essay, but a
brief digression is in order. First, we
may recall
The following example illustrates
the problem. Consider two bottles of
Chianti-Rufina standing next to one another on a table, one empty, the other
full; there is a difference, but it
would be obscure to claim there lies an authentic change between them. Yet,
suppose the sense in which one finds them ‘next’ to one another is temporal,
not spatial, for example, as seen in two still-lifes painted by an artist with
a penchant for veritas – such ‘change’
is common fare. So, what qualitatively
distinguishes these two cases – i.e., we say ‘spatial’ difference but ‘temporal’ change
– or is the distinction purely nominal?[6] I identify at least two explicit features: authentic change and the direction of process. However, not wishing to beg the question
before discussing direction, allow me
to propose another definition of authentic
change: a single token entity
manifesting as two or more inconsistent types. In the philosophy of mind, a ‘token’ denotes
a unique and particular or singular entity, whereas ‘type’ refers to a mould or
form, such as the class of full wine bottles with ‘Chianti-Rufina-1998’ etched
onto them. In the example above, the token is ‘this bottle of Chianti,’ and the two types separated by time are ‘full’ and ‘empty’ respectively.
While I choose to accept transience as
inevitably involving an (onto)-logical contradiction, there are many who impugn
such impossibility as absurd and, to their credit, not without good cause. In particular, a topic or object of discourse
only makes (scientific) sense if one can characterize its nature in a formal
language, whereas from an inconsistent phrase, anything and everything can be
logically adduced, with all the
pragmatic inadequacy this ‘explosiveness’ entails. Thus, the law of non-contradiction is a first
law in logic that one only perilously transgresses, and I suspect this accounts
for a good part of the reason why analytic philosophy has had such a difficult
time coming to terms with temporal transience (and perhaps love).
However, recent work in
‘paraconsistent logics’ suggests this law is not inscribed in stone, though I
have yet to find any of the developed logics satisfactory for the
characterization of transience.[7] Nevertheless, there are grounds for hope, for
the contradictions in question are marked by the order they are presented:
i.e., while a full bottle may become empty, or an empty bottle might become
full – both of which are only expressible in most logics as ‘bottle is full and empty’ or, equivalently, ‘bottle is
empty and full’ – we only wish at
most one of these contradictions to be true
per instance. Thus, it may prove
possible to control the aforementioned ‘explosiveness’ of our logic of
transience by introducing a non-commutative operator – e.g., an ampersand with
an arrow – that delimits verity to some, but not all, inconsistent expressions:
e.g., in this instance, ‘Full(Bottle)
&► Empty(Bottle),’
corresponding to ‘the full bottle becomes
an empty bottle,’ could be true, but ‘Empty(Bottle)
&►Full(Bottle)’
would remain false.
If this digression into formal logic
seems a trifle pedantic to some readers, I would assure them that it is difficult to
overestimate its importance here. The
scientific community can only investigate those ‘colours’ of nature that it can
articulate, disprove and corroborate clearly.
Furthermore, with respect to temporal transience, something else very
interesting appears in the logical arrangements I have been considering. It may be the case – possibly provable – that any logic capable of
expressing transience in a useful manner will intrinsically comprise features
that correspond in a natural way to what I introduce in the next section as directionality. If correct, it follows that all rhealogical
models of time manifest direction.
Moreover, such ‘direction’ may prove ineffable in purely chronological
logics – i.e., those that do not permit sentences expressing the kind of
inconsistency introduced earlier – in which case, only rhealogical models of time will be authentically
directed. Such a mutual logical
entailment remains conjecture for now, since the full arguments range beyond
the scope of this essay. On the other
hand, the views espoused here are hardly revolutionary; indeed, Kant long ago
recognized the logical relationship implicit between direction, transience and
inconsistency.[8]
1.2 Directedness and the Arrows of Time
This brings us to the issue of the
arrow of time or, more precisely, the directedness
of time. Fraser maintains that a ‘short
arrow’ first appears in biotemporality,
and Rovelli similarly attributes such to thermodynamics. (ibid.) However, there is already a direction
intrinsic to all of Fraser’s nested hierarchy defined by the generative
progression of evermore complex, nested models of time. This is thus well in accord with our working
hypothesis that temporal directedness and rhealogical time mutually entail one
another. Furthermore, I maintain there
is in fact no directedness in any of Rovelli’s models of temporality; his arrow
of time is only an asymmetry. To
appreciate this, a clearer distinction between directedness and asymmetry
should be drawn. Consider the following image:
Does it define a direction?
Figure 1.
Anyone licensed to drive an automobile probably feels it does point to the right, but this is a
cultural artefact, a mere convention. On
the other hand, the property of asymmetry
is rather intrinsic to the geometry of the shape itself, independently of our
interpretation. Thus, while it may be
that all instances of directedness may logically imply a measure of asymmetry,
the inverse is apparently not the case.[9] This property of directedness begs further
explication, but let us first consider it in the context of the arrow of time.
There is a rather extensive
literature concerned with the so-called ‘arrow of time,’ but from the beginning,
much of it fails even to recognize the term is a misnomer.[10]
Really, there is a quiver of
double-headed arrows, which are typically, but inexplicably, presumed to aim
together at a single target, namely, the
end of time, thereby supporting the
contention that there is some intrinsic directedness
to time. However, most of these putative
arrows are mere asymmetries, as illustrated in the table below.[11]
1. Psychological arrow: a directed asymmetry reflecting the ‘feeling of relentless forward temporal progression, according to which potentialities seem to be transformed into actualities.’
1a. Ontological asymmetry: a determinate past contrasted with an open future.
1b. Epistemic asymmetry: exemplified by memory, that we know more about the past than the future.
1c. Causal arrow: the direction in which events as effects seem to follow causes.
2. Entropic asymmetry: associated with second law of thermodynamics.
3. Electromagnetic asymmetry: radiation never ‘converges’ on an antenna in phase, but frequently ‘emits’ thus: only retarded solutions of Maxwell’s equations, and not advanced ones, are real.
4. Neutral Kaon asymmetry: the neutral K meson anomalously decomposes into pions at a rate that varies with the temporal direction of the process.
5. Relativistic asymmetry: some world lines end (begin) at singularities in black holes.
6. Cosmological asymmetry: corresponding to the expansion or contraction of the universe—i.e., the big bang vs. the big crunch (or its lack, as the case may be).
7. Quantum asymmetry: disputatiously resulting in quantum measurement.
8. Biological asymmetry: corresponding to evolutionary features of biological systems and organisms.
Naturally, some of these arrows may reduce to or derive from one
another, and this list is not intended to be complete; our concern here is with
directedness, or its lack, and this
becomes yet more transparent in the following thought experiment. Suppose that after much laudable science,
seven independent asymmetries were discovered to remain: Which direction does time tend? If each is thought to point in one of two
directions, then there would be 27 =
128 possible combinations, and in only two would all seven converge. The moral of the story is that ‘forward’ is
trivialized as conventional, and so most research on the arrow of time only concerns
the asymmetric distributions of properties across space-time; it says nothing
about temporal directedness. (Price
1996; Sklar 1974: 355-60) The only
feature of time that clearly incorporates an intrinsic direction is its perceived flux!
Thus, we should proceed carefully, for much like Augustine’s celebrated dictum
about time, that we only know it when we do not ask too much of it, closer
inspection similarly reveals directedness
to be a surprisingly Janus-faced concept.
1.3 Causality, Intentionality and the
Mathematical Infinite
Thus, let us broaden the scope of
our investigation and consider all possible instances of directedness in our
experience. In the first category, I take
it as given that we (human beings) all perceive
the passage of time as directed. We may
designate a second class, if we accept a generative theory of causality into
our physics (cf. 1c in the previous table), for then the cause-effect
relationship is also directed; i.e., causal events may exist independently of their
corresponding effectual events, but the latter only exist (are generated) through
the action of the former. However, the
vast majority of instances of directedness fall under the third grouping, intentionality, either explicitly or
implicitly.
The term ‘intentionality’ finds most
of its employment in the cognitive sciences and the philosophy of mind, and its
definition and nature are highly disputatious.
Nevertheless, ‘about-ness’ is an approximate synonym, and we are
referring to intentional relationships when we say a word is about its denotation, a thought is about its content and an image is about whatever it reproduces. In each case, there is nothing physical, but the metaphysical
significance of language, signs, and thoughts begs further explanation. Although intentionality is generally regarded
as an essential component of consciousness,
its etymology suggests a more general interpretation: the Latin word, intendo, means ‘to point at,’ which is rather
how Aquinas and his medieval, scholastic colleagues employed it in their
metaphysical musings. Such directedness
remains in the signification of contemporary ‘intentionality,’ for the about-ness relationship is intrinsically
uni-directional: e.g., the word ‘wine’ may be about the preferably red liquid often found in glass bottles, but
it is nonsensical to suppose such a beverage is about a four-letter concatenation.
Now, thinking back to the
right-handed arrow that figured earlier, a little reflection finds almost all
instances of perceived or posited direction are conventional. This means they derive their putative
direction from the way we, as intentional agents, interpret them; they are secondary qualities, to use Locke’s nomenclature. Thus, most empirical instances of direction vicariously
reduce to such a phenomenological subclass subsumed under intentionality,
without which all conventions would cease to exist. One might well argue that all instances of
directedness are dependent on intentionality in this way, but that presupposes
directedness is always a secondary quality, hence extrinsic to the natural
order, and this is refuted by the intrinsic directedness of intentionality, qua
natural kind. Nevertheless, the onus remains on us to demonstrate
which instances are intrinsic to nature, where directedness proves to be a primary quality. Besides intentionality itself, the only
physical possibilities seem to be time and causality, and only provided they
respectively prove to be rhealogical and generative.
This completes my inductive argument
with respect to ‘physical’ instances of direction, but there still remains a
putative fourth category that bears mentioning.
Certain mathematical structures intimate direction, at least as
symbolically expressed. Prima facie, an
infinite sequence of points with a proper limit form a set that can only be
articulated in one direction; i.e., the sequence (1, ½, ⅓, ¼,…) with 0 as a limit cannot be expressed beginning with its end point. Yet better examples may be found in logic,
such as recursively constructed Gödel-sentences. However, even if there exist mathematical objects
as natural kinds (Platonism), it is still not self-evident in what sense the
referents of mathematical language are directed, for such appearances may
result from the choice of mathematical language employed in their description,
in which case the directedness would be a secondary quality and so subsumed
under intentionality. On the other hand,
this seems less plausible with respect to the Gödel sentences noted above,
whose construction might well demonstrate an ostensible intrinsic directedness
that belongs to some kind of existent symbolic domain – if Platonism proves
correct in this way. However,
mathematical realism can take still several forms, many of which do not affect
the pursuant arguments of the next section significantly.
1.4 Memory and Time
Memories are variously the thoughts,
feelings, signifiers and other instances of manifest information that refer to
events properly attributed to the past.
As such, they compose a subspecies of intentions, but they have a double relationship with time. Firstly, as intentions, they are intrinsically directed, and I will argue that
this entails an intimate relationship with rhealogical temporality. Secondly, they comprise an important subset
of intentional vectors that refer to (define?) the chronological past.
Thus we find a curious metaphysical
circularity in the way memory and time support and refer back to one
another. Past events and entities prove
the most ambiguously existential (actual) of all potentialities, since their
status in this respect is largely derived from memory. Yet, the liminal reality of
that-which-has-gone-before is essential to the causal determination of all
present identities, including the very intentional
agency that creates those memories.
Thus, the following three questions are posed: How does man create
memories? How do memories and the past
correspond? How does the past determine
man? Such circularity suggests that
memories, along with their symmetric counterparts, expectations, play an especially interesting role, both in the marriage
of rhealogical and chronological temporalities – whose union we may call ‘time’
– and in the metaphysical integration and explication of mind and body. Moreover, because memories are arguably
ostensibly empirical, they demonstrate the deficiency of contemporary scientific
theories to account in ‘monochromatic’ terms for the spectrum of ‘colourful’
mental phenomena evident in nature.
2. Synthesis of Rhealogical Time,
Intentionality and Causality
I have thus far argued inductively
that these three categories are sufficient to account for all physical instances
of directedness, and I have conjectured with some supporting rational that
transience and the (directed) arrow of time mutually entail one another. We may now turn to three further methodological
arguments, each respectively linking our conceptions of time, causality and
intentionality together into a larger logical-conceptual synthesis. The first shows a general correspondence
between models of generative causality and rhealogical temporality; the second
correlates such causality with intentionality; and the third argues that our
ontological commitments to intentionality and time are strongly interdependent. This sets of the stage for last section’s
conclusions about the natures of memory, agency, physical reality and time.
2.1 Temporality and Causality
If the model of time employed to describe a set of events is genuinely
directed, this suffices to introduce directedness into a causal scheme on those
events. Similarly, a genuinely directed
theory of causality suffices to construct a directed model of time.
Causal theories come in two shades:
either they are generative (colourful)
or correlative (monochromatic). Aristotle’s views exemplify the former,
whereas Hume’s paradigmatizes the latter; the key difference lies in that
correlative, ‘scientific’ causality does not qualitatively differentiate
between counter-factual causes and causes simplicitor, undermining the
important intuition that causes precede
effects, but not visa-versa.
The inability of such ‘scientific’
models of causality to demonstrate intrinsic direction appears to result from
their underlying assumptions, which allow them in general to be expressed in a
first order language. For if we suppose TC is such a causal theory
with axioms, events {ei} and n-relationships C(causes; effect), in general, an inverse theory TC-1
is constructible that is satisfied by
the same structures as TC; i.e., Mod(TC) = Mod(TC-1). This is accomplished by defining C-1(effects;
causes) so that is satisfied. Such formalism is simply a long-winded way of
articulating how the causal arrows between events can be reversed without
injury to the expressiveness of a first order causal theory, because the direction
of the relations between events are superfluous to the correlations, as
illustrated below:
Figure 2.
Yet, we wish to explain the origin
of the apparent direction and order of the many causal relationships we
commonly experience. Hume grounded such
structural features in temporality as he experienced it, which was
psychological, hence transient and rhealogical. (Hume, 2000) Similarly, most contemporary theories follow
suit, for as Reichenbach observed, ‘Time… represents not only an ordered series
generated by an asymmetrical relation, but is also unidirectional. This fact is
usually ignored. We often say simply: the direction from earlier to later
events, from cause to effect is the direction of the progress of time.’ (1958: 138-39) And, indeed, if time describes a manifold
with an engraved direction and includes every physical event, it follows
trivially that the said direction maps onto any subset of those of events characterized
in a causal theory or relationship.
Thus, rhealogical time suffices to account for the directedness of
causality.
This state of affairs would all be
fine and well, but the problem deepens considerably when an origin for temporal
direction is sought. As discussed
earlier, the physical arrows of time provide no answers, and a suitable
scientific account founded on a chronological conception of time has proven
sufficiently vexing, that several thinkers have rather attempted to derive the
latter’s structure from the ‘natural’ order and direction of causality. (Bunge
1959; Tooley 1997;1999) Indeed, if we
suppose the cosmos is composed of some set of events arranged as a directed causal
lattice, its order and direction can
be homomorphed back onto those events, introducing a
directed structure to time. In this case,
two events are said to be ‘simultaneous’ if-and-only-if they are identical or
do not belong to any common causal chain,
and an event is said to ‘precede’ another if-and-only-if it precedes that other
causally on such a chain. Finally, the temporal orientation of an event
corresponds to the direction of causal relations to which the event
belongs. Thus, the directedness of an
ontological account of causality suffices for a corresponding structure of time.
However, the articulation of a
directed causal theory is fraught with the same logical difficulties facing the
explication of rhealogical time. As the
logical argument and illustration above make abundantly clear, any meaningful,
generative causal theory will require new methods and formalization. It is perhaps for this reason that, by and
large, generative theories of causality found their greatest circulation in the
pre-Leibnizian – and so pre-symbolic and pre-scientific – era of the medieval
scholastics. And overlooking these factors
in would-be generative theories of causality has tended to undermine some of
the most interesting attempts to explain our experience of time.
Finally, let me conclude
here with a brief note on so-called ‘backward causation,’ which is code in much
physical literature for time travel into the past, and which also indicates how
physics largely understands the structure of time to derive from the causal
relationships between events. Leaving
the issues associated with causal paradoxes aside for now – the rhealogical-chronological
modelling of time may shed much light here, but the discussion would take us
too far a field in this essay, since it begs important questions about freewill
– there are no significant problems introduced to this account of the
relationship between time and causality.
If an event in a directed causal sequence of events is also its own
cause, then the structure introduced onto time will be circular and closed, but
directed all the same.
2.2 Causality and Intentionality
Naturally occurring causal directedness suffices to account for the
directedness of intentionality. Similarly,
the directedness of intentionality suffices to explain the appearance of causal
directedness in nature.
Intentionality is a primary property of
consciousness and, adopting a naturalist position, is generated from a
composite of processes and elements in the (human) brain. Explaining the emergence of consciousness from
matter has a long history as the mind-body problem in philosophy, and it has
shown itself remarkably resilient to resolution. However, if we accept that mind
supervenes on the physical body and
brain, then the web of experiences, feelings, memories and thoughts must map into
some corresponding set of embodied processes. If those underlying parts then interact in a
genuinely-directed causal manner, it follows that such interactions will similarly
transpose onto the elements of mentality, providing a plausible account of the directedness
of intentionality.
Let us consider an example that does
not stray too far from a number of current cognitive theories. Let M1
be an experienced memory that reminds us of another memory M2, and each intentionally signifies some objects, O1 and O2, which in turn likely signify other memories or
experiences, which in turn refer to yet other objects, O11 and O21,
etc.. Ultimately, I postulate such a
chain of signification yields a web of objects, which at certain loci start to
take on the characteristics of physical events, E1 and E2,
the putative referents of memories, M1
and M2. When these events actually occurred – so the
theory goes – they left causal impressions on the brain, affecting brain
states, B1 and B2, though both are also
affected by all the elements of the chain of objects. Per our assumptions above, these are the two
physically instantiated brain states upon which our two respective memories
putatively supervene. There is then a web of relationships – which,
in vivo, would be complex to a degree
beyond description – but isolating an absurdly simplified example, I illustrate
below the different kinds of directed relations to consider, namely,
intentional (unbroken lines), causal (dashed) and mixed:
Figure 3.
I propose here that the origin of the direction
of intentionality naturally obtains from the directedness of physical
causality. This follows directly for the
M1-M2 mental
relation of remembering, since it is isomorphic to the B1-B2 physical causal relation. Similarly, the E1-E2 about-ness
relationship, for example characterizing the signifier and signified of a word
and its imagined association, may similarly derive its direction as an analogue
of the original B1-B2
relationship. The M1-O1 and M2-O2 intentional relationships, which seem
to tend against the grain are more subtle to explain. However, all of the objects, Oxy, synchronously represent
both physical brain states and quasi-mental states (many perhaps not properly
conscious as such), and so there are ample resources to sum over the many
interrelated vectors to produce the requisite directedness. Nevertheless, what is most significant to
appreciate from this illustration is that the directedness of intentionality
need not be miraculously generated ex
nihilo. Thus, a genuinely directed
theory of causality suffices to explain the origin of intentional
direction.
We might pause to consider here
whether the reverse does not also obtain, that intentionality might similarly
account for the apparent directedness of causality. Indeed, the logic appears symmetric. However, it resembles the highly mystical
metaphysics of many pre-scientific cultures, for the causal interactions of
physical processes then result from the dynamics of purely intentional,
spirit-like entities, manitous. On the
other hand, just because an idea is old does not mean it is irrelevant.
Alternatively, there is an epistemic
correlate to the previous ontological argument.
Since all theories of nature are conceived through the lenses of intentional
minds, it is not such a stretch to claim we anthropomorphize and baptize a direction as the direction. This remains
especially plausible so long as physics remains ambiguous on the matter, which
indeed it does:
Figure 4.
Above, ‘causally’ related events (E),
experienced states (S) and physical
phenomena of some asymmetric class (X)
are all respectively simultaneous at times (t). Such asymmetric ‘arrows’ are the closest
contemporary science comes to explicating causality, but they all fail to
account for its apparent directedness, whatever may be claimed.[12] The alternative anchors our experience of
causality in our psychology, though the ontological origin of its directedness
is then begged of intentionality itself.
Nevertheless, whether it is physics appealing to intentionality and
psychology for the apparent directedness of causality, or psychology referring
back to physical causality to ground the directedness of mental processes, both
demonstrate an intimate relationship between domains.
2.3 Intentionality, Consciousness and
Rhealogical Time
The genuine, intrinsic directedness of intentionality is sufficient to
account for the apparent directedness of time.
On the other hand, if time is genuinely directed, it suffices to account
for the directedness of intentionality.
Cartesian dualism splits mentality and
physicality in a way that almost perfectly parallels the schism between
rhealogical (psychological) time and chronological (physical) time. However, here it becomes important to
distinguish between consciousness and intentionality, which is arguably only
one important aspect of the former; others include qualia, agency, freewill, and self-consciousness. Similarly, the directed arrow of time is only
one aspect of rhealogical temporality, which also comprises such other aspects
as transience and the distinction or dimension of actua et potentia. Now, a satisfactory analysis (and subsequent
synthesis) of these two domains is beyond the scope of this essay, but a few
remarks may suffice to sketch the argument.
Mentality derives much of its
physical significance from its capacity to realize the future and past in the
present, through memory, prediction, differentiation, association,
identification and other intentional actions.
How does it do this? Indeed, the
physical significance of one workman calling out to another, ‘slab!’ – to
recall Wittgenstein’s example – correlates strongly with the likelihood that
the other will in fact give the first a slab in the future. (1958) Without
wishing to oversimplify a matter that is really considerably more complex, an
important way intentionality obtains physical significance lies in connecting
agency, identity and signs in the present moment with events of the past and
future and, moreover, predictably affecting the constitution of that future.[13]
In sum, I claim thus that a
conscious agency without an intrinsic capacity to refer or associate in a
unidirectional manner would, nevertheless, be able to recreate that
directedness if it were subject to rhealogical process in time. Here, the identities of all elements,
physical and mental, are subject to a uni-directional evolution – i.e., they
either persist or they change – provided we accept the conjecture introduced in
section 1.1. However, it then follows
that an association between two possible identities belonging to different
moments of time are distinguishable in that the one can become the other, but
not vice versa. From here, all species
of directed intentions, including memories, can be created and recreated through
the faculties of creative imagination and identification. Again, the difficult step is to derive an
initial directedness ex nihilo, and the posited directedness of time provides
the needed pigment to colour the remainder of the ontology.
Suppose on the other hand we imagine
the reverse scenario: a universe devoid of rhealogical temporality, but
inhabited by intentional agency.
Interestingly, Weyl describes such a world when he famously writes,
The
objective world simply is, it does not happen.
Only to the gaze of my consciousness, crawling upward along the lifeline
of my body, does a section of this world come to life as a fleeting image in
space which continuously changes in time. (Weyl 1963: 116)
Here, time is characterized as purely chronological, but can consciousness
survive embedded in such a spatialized block-universe?[14] I contend that it is not possible and so
conclude that rhealogical time is essential to consciousness and
intentionality.
Assuming the postulates of cognitivism
for the nonce, mentality derives from information
instantiated in some physical material, whether that be carbon-based biology,
silicon-based technology or wood-based tinker-toys. Since the choice of material is
inconsequential, I will follow Leibniz’s example and choose wood on aesthetic
grounds to construct a hypothetically sentient machine.[15]
Indubitably, such a ‘consciousness’
would be massive and complex, but engineering issues aside, its design falls
within the parameters of cognitivism, the popular view today in those academic
circles dedicated to creating artificial intelligence and explaining the
evolution of mind in the cosmos. Thus,
let us baptize him ‘Tinky,’ the timeless,
tinker-toy boy. Now, what environmental
conditions are required for Tinky to tick?
Presumably, at each chronological
moment, Tinky realizes a corresponding physical structure, so that his genidentity is composed of a series of
states foliated along the ‘temporal’ dimension space-time. However, as time is chronological, it has
equivalent properties with space. Thus, there
is no reason to believe Tinky’s psychological constitution would be affected by
transposing his physical parts onto spatial dimensions only. Admittedly, some contortion may be necessary,
but we may assume enough ‘temporal’ thickness to maintain his structural
integrity. Now, the problem is to
identify, in principle, any indication of Tinky’s sentience in this static,
spatialized state; even a hint of the directedness intrinsic to his putative
intentionality would suffice.
However, isolating his intentionality’s
physical origin in such a crystallized, inert state is absurd. His genidentical body is composed of alternating
regions of space and material at best asymmetrically distributed. What geometric form can, even in principle,
signify directedness? Any mark or
pattern like ‘►’ that we might discover uncovers
nothing because, as discussed earlier, such symbols do not intrinsically
signify anything, least of all direction.
Whatever ecstasy Tinky experienced during his short lived temporal
interval, there remains no corresponding physical trace of it or his intentionality, contretemps with
cognitivism. Thus, I conclude that the
constitution of memory and intentionality apparently require more than material
and information; some tertiary ingredient is required, and the most plausible
candidate is the directed process of rhealogical time.
3. Conclusions
Time, causality and intentionality
intersect in many ways, sharing structural symmetries and
ontological-existential similarities, but no scientifically established theory
is available to explain them. However,
their global and synthetic consideration together suggests a deeper ontological
relationship, as illustrated below:
Figure 5.
I have considered how these three doubled arrows coalesce and how each
finds resolution in the other. Thus,
each individual plausibility thesis contributes to a collective corroboration
of the others, and it suggests strong grounds that the directedness of
causality, time and intentionality all share a common ontological origin. This view has been espoused by others, such
as J. R. Lucas, albeit argued differently, but it has yet to be aggressively
pursued.[16] This results in a great part, because so
little is really understood about the brain, mind and time. Yet,
Time is the
brain’s glue… The experience of time is a neurophysiological construction that
is generated actively within our brain, but how this is accomplished no one
really knows… the sense of time follows from intentionality but the links that
translate such a neural process into a subject experience are unknown. (Modell
2002, 34)
Indeed, there is growing recognition that these ‘perennial’ mysteries are
related.
So, where does that
leave us in this search? Firstly, I have
argued that we are in fact searching for a single underlying principle. Secondly, this translates into refining the
methodological approaches adopted in each domain, that they better cohere. Thirdly, and most central to my thesis, each
of the three aforementioned domains bears sufficient similarity that we should
adopt a similar epistemic attitude toward them all.
Thus, if one feels compelled to
adopt mental eliminativism, which is akin to claiming there is no
intentionality, then the same view should be employed to characterize time and
causality. Similarly, a purely
chronological modelling of time or a blanket prohibition on directed causality
will undermine the other two, respectively.
On the other hand, if one finds the experience of self-consciousness,
time or physical causality as directed more convincing, then it behooves one to
meditate carefully on the natures of all three.
In this way, a stronger empirical case is presented on account that
evidence for any one of the three problem sets becomes evidence for all three,
and this very much undermines such eliminativist views to my mind. Not only does the world appear in spectacular
Technicolor, ‘monochromatic’ theories that deny it are now trebly wrong.
However, in tracing the ontological
and theoretical relationships between these three puzzling domains, more than
such a denial follows. The similarity
between these quandaries suggests that whichever approach one adopts in one
domain, methodological consistency would demand a similar epistemic attitude
towards the other two. Thus, if a mysterion view of mind seems closest to
correct in the case of consciousness, corresponding antirealist accounts would
best serve in explaining the natures of time and causality. Similarly, functionalist interpretations of any one of the three problem sets
should stand or fall together with corresponding theories in the other
domains. By extension, we may then include
such paradigms as mechanism and materialism.
I remain tentatively optimistic
about the potential of science to uncover much of the underlying nature of
temporality, causality, and intentionality.
However, this will only become possible once its institutionalized
monochromatic glasses are removed and some of the most difficult questions resolutely
posed: e.g., what is directedness and where does it come from? Although its definition is subtle, its
empirical merit and pragmatic value are not easily denied. Moreover, as noted, mathematics indirectly
expresses directedness in some of its formalisms. So, features of the universe necessitating
models with such formalisms suggest themselves for further research.
However, if such colour proves
finally beyond the purview of a strictly monochromatic science, at the least, I
leave the sciences and the arts and humanities somewhat better defined and
delineated, if not bridged. In that
unhappy future, the sciences can continue to treat time as an empty chronological
canvas, the mind as an inconvenient distraction from the truth and causality as
code for the many statistical correlations that compose the cosmos. And the arts and humanities?
Wonderful colours.
References
Beall, J. C., 2004. Introduction:
At the Intersection of Truth and Falsity. In The Law of Non-Contradiction: New Philosophical Essays, edited by
Priest, Graham, Beall, J. C. and Armour-Garb, Bradley.
Bunge, Mario, 1959,1979. Causality and Modern Science, 3rd
revised edition.
Čapek, Milek, 1961. The
Philosophical Impact of Contemporary Physics. Princeton; NJ:
Davies, Paul, 2002. That Mysterious Flow. Scientific American (September, 2002).
Douglas, E. R., 2005. Rhealogical & Chronological Time: a Titanic Marriage. Submitted to Kronoscope, found in http://www.philosophyoftime.org/rhealogical.html.
Fraser, J. T., 1999. Time, Conflict and Human Values.
________, 1998. From Chaos to Conflict. In Time, Order, Chaos: The Study of Time IX,
edited by Fraser, J. T., Soulsby, P. and Argyros, A.. Madison: International
University Press.
________, 1996. Time and the Origin of Life.
In Dimensions of Time and Life: The Study
of Time VIII, edited by Fraser, J. T. and Soulsby, M..
________, 1987. Time: the Familiar Stranger.
________, 1975. Of Time, Passion and Knowledge.
Freeman, Walter, 2000. Perception of Time and Causation through Kinaesthesia of Intentional Action. Journal of Cog. Proc. 1.
Goodman, Nelson, 1977. The Structure of Appearance, 3rd edition.
Hameroff, Stuart, 2001. Time,
Consciousness and Quantum Events in Fundamental Space-time Geometry. In The Nature of Time: Geometry, Physics and Perception, edited by Buccheri, R., Saniga, M.
and Stuckey, W.
Hawking, Stephen, Laflamme, R. and Lyons,
G.W., 1993. The Origin of Time Asymmetry. Preprint found in http://lanl.arxiv.org/PS_cache/gr-qc/pdf/9301/9301017.pdf
Hume, David, 2000. A Treatise of Human Nature. Edited
by Norton, D.F. and Norton, M..
Jackson, Frank, 1986. What Mary Didn't Know. The Journal of Philosophy LXXXIII, 5
(May 1986):291-95.
Kant, Immanuel, 1998. Critique of Pure Reason. Translated and edited by Guyer, Paul and
Wood, Allen W..
Leibniz, Gottfried, 1714; Monadology. Reprinted in Philosophical Writings: Leibniz, edited
by Dent, J. M., 1995. Everyman’s Library,
Lucas, J., 1999. A Century of Time. In The Arguments of Time, edited by Butterfield, Jeremy and Isham,
Chris.
McTaggart, John, 1908. The Unreality of Time. Mind 17: 457-74.
Modell, A., 2002. Intentionality and the Experience of Time. Kronoscope 2(1):21-39.
Newton-Smith, W.H., 1980. The
Structure of Time.
Oaklander, Nathan, 1984. Temporal
Relations and Temporal Becoming: A Defense of a Russellian Theory of Time.
Øhrstrøm, Peter and Hasle, P.,
1995. Temporal Logic: From Ancient Ideas
to Artificial Intelligence.
Park, David,
1996. Consciousness and the Individual Event in Scientific Theory. In Dimensions
of Time and Life: The Study of Time VIII, edited by Fraser, J. T. and Soulsby,
M..
_______, 1972. The
Myth of the Passage of Time. In The Study
of Time, edited by Fraser, J. T., Haber, F. C. and Müller, G. H..
Penrose, Roger, 1994. Shadows
of the Mind.
Priest, Graham, 2004. What’s So
Bad About Contradictions? In The Law of
Non-Contradiction: New Philosophical Essays, edited by Priest, Graham,
Beall, J. C. and Armour-Garb, Bradley.
Price, Hew, 1996. Time’s Arrow
and Archimedes’ Point: New Directions for the Physics of Time.
_______, 1995. Cosmology, Time’s Arrow and the Double Standard. In Time’s Arrows Today: Recent Physical and
Philosophical Work on the Direction of Time, edited by Savitt, Steve.
_______, 1989. A Point on the Arrow of Time. Nature (July, 1989):181-182.
Reichenbach, H.,
1958. The Philosophy of Space and Time.
Rovelli, Carlo, 1995. Analysis of the
Distinct Meanings of the Notion of <<Time>> in Different Physical
Theories. Il Nuovo Cimento vol.110B,n.1.
Savitt, Steven, 1995. Introduction to Time’s Arrows Today: Recent Physical and Philosophical Work on the
Direction of Time, edited by Savitt,
Steve.
Schlesinger, George, 1980. Aspects
of Time.
Schulman, L.S., 1997. Time’s
Arrows and Quantum Measurement.
Sklar, Lawrence, 1974. Space,
Time, Space-time.
Taylor, Richard, 1955. Spatial and Temporal
Analogies and the Concept of Identity. Philosophy LII.
Tooley, Michael, 1999. The Metaphysics of
Time. In The Arguments of Time,
edited by Butterfield, Jeremy and Isham, Chris.
_______, 1997. Time, Tense
& Causation.
Webster’s Third New
International Dictionary, 1993.
Weyl, Hermann, 1963. The
Philosophy of Mathematics and Natural Science.
Wittgenstein, Ludwig, 1958. Philosophical
Investigations. Translated by Anscomb, G. E. M..
[1] Many scientists of course do tacitly accept this point, even celebrating science as a product of a humanist cultural revolution against the medieval metaphysics that preceded it. Nevertheless, there are no mainstream scientific methodologies that legitimize themselves as objects of their study. Indubitably, the sophists would not approve.
[2] This metaphor of colour may be
more than a metaphor. In his argument
against physicalism, the philosopher of mind, Frank Jackson proposes a
celebrated thought experiment: Mary is a woman of the future who knows all there
is ‘scientifically’ to know about colour, but she herself is colorblind, and so
limited to a physicalist vocabulary to explain the phenomena. (
[3] Schulman
analogizes speculative philosophy as “scouting” new terrain, leading the way
for the “heavy-tanks” of physics (his discipline) to follow. (1997) While I regard the military metaphor as a
trifle extreme, there is much to be said for philosophy that does not limit its
scope only to what can be proved.
[4] The term, ‘rhealogical,’ is a neologism
I introduce to characterize a class of models of time that compliments
especially Bergson’s use of ‘chronological.’
It avoids many semantic pitfalls prevalent amongst temporal terminology
by addressing the essential property of authentic change (which I discuss in
this essay). The etymology is both the
Greek word, rhein, meaning to flow
(as in ‘time flows’), but it also nicely dovetails with the name of the
titan-goddess Rhea, who was sister and wife to Kronos, god of time. For further discussion on the nature and
significance of rhealogical models of time, see
[5] cf.
Park (1996; 1972). Similarly, in the
only article to address transience in Scientific American’s most recent issue dedicated to time, Davies summarily dismisses it as an
illusion: ‘Nothing in known physics
corresponds to the passage of time. Indeed, physicists insist that time doesn’t
flow at all; it merely is.’ (2002)
[6]
The view I am
confuting here is nicely summarized in Oaklander’s conclusion to his refutation
of A-series interpretations of time: ‘What distinguishes greater than among
numbers from later than among events?
…only the relation itself… [which] is a simple and unanalyzable
relation. Thus, there is nothing that we
can say about temporal succession that would distinguish it phenomenologically
from other relations that have the same logical properties. Nevertheless, succession is something more
than its logical properties and we all know what more it is although we cannot
say… There is no further basis for the
difference between temporal and non-temporal relations with the same logical
properties, they are just different.’ (Oaklander 1984: 17)
[7] For a good introduction to
paraconsistent logics and the problems facing their construction, see Beall
(2004) and Priest (2004).
[8] Kant
identifies both the issue of inconsistency and that of direction or order: “…the concept of motion, as alteration of place, is possible only
through and in the representation of time… render[ing] comprehensible… a
combination of contradictorily opposed predicates in one and the same object,
namely, one after the other. Thus
our concept of time explains the possibility of… motion…” (Kant 1998:
B48-49)
[9] Logically,
let direction be a relation, D( , ), of elements, e1
and
e2. All we can infer
about the finite models that satisfy it is asymmetry,
because we can construct an inverse expression, D-1( , ),
representing the opposite direction, such that:
╞ D(e1 , e2 ) if and only if ╞ D-1(e2
, e1 ).
[10] Although
the ‘arrow of time’ has entered the common vocabulary, its meaning remains very
disputatious in both philosophy and physics. (Hawking 1995, Price 1996; 1995;
Savitt 1995; Schulman 1997; Sklar 1974) It originally appears as ‘Time’s Arrow’
on p.28 of Eddington’s 1928 Gifford Lectures. (Savitt 1995: 1)
[11] Roger
Penrose distinguishes between three aspects similar to 1a-c. (1979: 591) Also, if the seventh, quantum asymmetry should
prove genuine, then it may well be moreover directed, depending on whether one
interprets the collapse of the wave function as an ontological event – cf. (Penrose
1994).
[12] Hawking writes, ‘The psychological arrow, our subjective sense of time, the fact that we remember events in one direction of time but not the other,… [and] the electromagnetic arrow… can be shown to be consequences of the thermodynamic arrow, which says that entropy is increasing in one direction of time.’ (1993: 3) However, he never does tell how this is done, as Price notes. (1995,1989)
[13] Freeman
maintains psychological time is rooted in future-directed intentionality. (2000)
As Modell writes, ‘The emergence of a
goal thrusts the organism’s past into its future.’ (2002: 22) Similarly, Peirce writes, ‘One of the most
marked features about the law of mind is that it makes time to have a definite
direction of flow from past to future.’ (Øhrstrøm 1995: 133) For
further research that intimates a deep connection between time and mind, see
Penrose (1994), Hameroff (2001).
[14] cf. Schlesinger writes, ‘a spatial world in which time did not exist would be entirely stripped of capacity to contain the basic ingredients of a viable universe.’ (1980: 18)
[15] cf. Leibniz’s comparison of the mind to a windmill. (1714)
[16] Lucas
similarly argues for an ontological integration of time, consciousness, and
causality, though not via directedness. (1999)